CMS150 - Winter 2001

Trials of Conscience: Litigation

and the Rhetoric of Identity

 Week 2, Class 1 Lecture Outline

1/16/01


Background Notes for the Apology

  • The parties to the litigation
    • Meletus was probably the son of a tragic poet of the 5th century whom Aristophanes mocked for his dullness, immorality and scrawny appearance (but remember, this is like Jay Leno ridiculing a popular writer today (e.g., Stephen King &endash; how accurate the humor is, is hard to say). He would have been quite young at the time of Socrates's trial in 399 and was/was not [??]the same person as the Meletus who accused Andocides of impiety around the same time [nb &endash; Andocides had been a member of an oligarch club accused of the mutilation of the Hermes and profanation of the Mysteries; and who ratted out his friends; Andocides was aquitted of the charge [impiety]. The convential wisdom is that the Meletus of Plato's Apology, was the tool of Anytus, Socrates' real opponent.

    • Anytus, was a wealthy Athenian and a leader of the democratic party. He and Thrasybulus were the leaders who restored democratic rule to Athens after the Thirty Tyrants. He was fairly moderate in his beliefs and politics except for a passionate hatred for sophists whom he believed had led to the destruction of democracy in Athens. By prosecuting Socrates he hoped to ensure that sophists would no longer harm the democratic city. [nb &endash; whether or not you stayed in or fled the city under the Thirty became a "loyalty test" for some democrats]. Anytus was a tanner by profession and apparently extremely successful at his job (i.e., a member of the nouveau riche, not the traditional aristocracy). [Alternatively, his father was the successful tanner and his was the first generation of wealth and luxury in the family). There are two stories about him: first, that his own son was a devotee of Socrates for a while, to which Anytus strongly objected; second that Anytus was rich enough to bribe a jury in 410 when he was prosecuted for losing a battle. There are hints in Plato's dialogue, The Meno, that there is some basis in truth for the first story. The first instance of the bribery story appears in a work titled the Athenian Constitution which appears to have been written by students of Aristotle (a student of Plato) in 329/8 BCE (i.e., 70 years after Socrates' death). This story, however, is not mentioned in Xenophon (who surely would have seized the opportunity to impugn the integrity of Socrates' accusor), and should probably be considered part of the "backlash" tradition that Plato especially helped to create (the Romans had numerous stories about how the accusers came to bad ends).

    • Lycon - We don't know anything

    • You tell me. For ideas, consult:
  • The Charge of asebia
    • The prosecutors brought a graphe asebias [a "written charge of impiety"; = "indictment"] against Socrates. Athenian law tends to define procedure more than it does substance. In other words, the law of asebia says, "if a man commits asebia, one may bring a graphe against him." Because the definition of substance is left to each individual jury [this conduct is asebia, that is not], juries had extraordinary power in Athenian political life. Unlike modern western systems there was no doctrine of precedent (i.e., courts consider themselves bound by what previous courts had done in similar cases). While litigants knew and argued, "juries have always considered this conduct to be asebia (or theft, or murder, etc), and while juries were open to such arguments, they were not required to do what a previous jury had done.

    • There was one type of asebia that Athenian law specifically recognized &endash; stealing items from temples. We know from law court speeches that Athenians also considered it an act of asebia for a man to enter a temple if he was in a state of atimia.

    • Atimia was the partial or complete loss of civic rights that juries could impose as a sentence. [see, e.g., 30D] People who owed money to the government, for example, were in a state of atimia until they paid off the debt. People who were convicted of treason, bribery, cowardice in battle, perjury (3 convictions required) were deprived of all civic rights. Citizens could be deprived of some, but not all rights, for failure to prosecute law suits they had brought,; failure to win at least a fifth of the votes at trial; 3 convictions for proposing unconstitutional laws in the Assembly; certain moral offenses.

  • Athenian religious belief
    • Delphi was the site of an oracular shrine that was extremely important to all Greeks. The god Apollo spoke there through the Pythia. People (and this included everyone from women who had trouble to conceiving to heads of state and the Athenian assembly, went to Delphi or sent representatives there, to ask the Pythia a question. After appropriate gifts had been offered to the god, priests submitted the question to the Pythia and she, in a trance like state, responded (often in verse). What she said could be quite cryptic, or quite straightforward.

    • Religion in Greece and Rome, and most of the Mediterranean world was a matter of ritual practice not private belief. Ritual was how a community regulated its relationship with the gods. Failure to properly maintain that relationship would be disasterous for the community as a whole. Thus the community had a strong incentive to police religious behavior, because there was no guarantee that the gods wouldn't just punish the impious. They might punish the community for tolerating them. People who refused to participate in ritual or people who brought in new religious practices that the community as a whole did not review and approve, threatened the safety of everyone. Socrates religious behavior was suspect because a) the irony in his treatment of Delphi; b) the unusual nature of his discussion of his daemon; and c) the fact that Alcibiades was associated with the profanation of the Mysteries, the mutilation of the herms, and the loss of the Pelopponesean War.

  • Socratic irony and elenchus
    • Typically folks define irony as "say something, but mean it's contrary." Under this definition, when Socrates says that he is ignorant, he means he is wise; etc. According to Lloyd Spenser, the Danish philosopher Soren Kierkegaard defined Socratic irony as his conversational ploy of pretending to be ignorant about a subject. Rather than offer his own opinions on a subject, he cross examines people who claim to know about the subject (elenchus) about their ideas, demonstrates the inconsistancies of their ideas, and thereby demonstrates how pompous and foolish they are. Socratic irony, according to the philosopher Nehamas, however, is even more complicated than the "code" style definition of irony (i.e., Socrates says the opposite of what he means). We can't really just reverse everything Socrates says, and therefore assume we know what he meant. Rather than the opposite of what is said, in ironic statements we find Socratic silence; a silence that compels us to try and fashion meaning.

    • Elenchus was the method Socrates used to "cross-examine" his interlocutors who claimed to have some sort of wisdom. Claiming to possess no wisdom in their field (Socratic irony), he asked them to define in general terms what their wisdom was. They offered examples, and Socrates would insist that examples weren't good enough. The interlocutor would then offer a general definition of his field of expertise, or, more commonly, Socrates would offer a general definition which he would accept. Socrates would then ask them a series of yes/no questions which would lead inevitably to the conclusion that the general definition was wrong. This would lead to an aporetic state (aporia - "no way through") which would either frustrate and annoy the interlocutor or cause him to recognize that his assumptions had been false, and that he (like Socrates) was really ignorant. This state, in which one abandons his/her assumptions and preconceptions and recognizes his/her own ignorance, is the precondition to the pursuit of wisdom, according to Socrates.

  • The Trial of the Generals of the Arginusae
    • In 406 BCE the Athenian navy fought and won a significant naval victory over the Spartans called the Battle of the Arginusae. The 8 generals (the title was the same whether you commanded soldiers or sailors) present (2 were not there) decided to split the fleet, some ships sailing home, others picking up wounded and dead Athenians (for burial). After the fleet split, a great storm arose preventing the rescue and recovery of dead and wounded Athenians. When news reached Athens of the number of Athenians who had not been recovered or rescued a political cause celebre arose which some politicians manipulated for their own immediate political ends. Some politicians, supported by the people who had reached a furious outrage, insisted that six of the generals be tried and judged collectively (two had fled when they heard what was happening). This was absolutely against Athenian law and precedent (individuals charged with capital offenses had a right to have their cases heard individually). The generals were found guilty and killed. Subsequently the people realized that they had been manipulated by their leaders and found against those who had proposed the illegal procedures against the generals.

    • Socrates became involved in this issue by a fluke. The duties of organzing matters (e.g., setting agendas) to be considered at Assembly meetings rotated among the citizens. Socrates happened to have been chosen to be among the group of organizers (prytanes) for the month when the Trial of the Generals was opposed. It appears that he refused to perform the ministerial duty of announcing the agenda item (trying the generals collectively) to the Assembly and walked out of the meeting of the prytanes. Someone else did and the generals were subsequently executed.

  • The arrest of Leon of Salamis
    • After the Thirty Tyrants came to power in Athens, the asked Sparta to install a garrison of soldiers in the city to give them military support. They then took to killing their opponents without a trial. Within eight months they had executed 1,500 citizens and banished 5,000 others. The Thirty liked to implicate other Athenians in their actions.

      • In the case of one famous execution, for example, they brought the defendant, Theramenes, before a council of 500 citizens. The Thirty typically insisted that each member of the council publicly vote on their requests for executions. Those who refused to vote with them were identified as potential enemies. Those who did vote with them became a part of their unconstitutional activities. At the trial of Thereamenes (who himself had originally been a member of the Thirty, but alienated Critias, Plato's uncle and leader of the radical oligarchs, by opposing the frequency of executions) the Thirty took the precaution of filling the council chamber with Spartan soldiers and young aristocratic thugs who supported the Thirty. When Theramenes spoke well in his own defense and appeared to have won the sympathy of council of 500, Critias informed the council that Theramenes had lost all his civic rights (including the right to a trial) and that the Thirty condemned him to death. The thugs then dragged Theramenes from an altar, where he had claimed sanctuary, and forced him to drink hemlock.

      • The case of Leon of Salamis is another example of the Thirty attempting to implicate other Athenians in their unconstitutional methods. They summoned five citizens to their chambers and ordered them to arrest Leon of Salamis (a wealthy metic, i.e., resident alien, who lived in a suburb of Athens). Those summoned knew that Leon would be executed without trial (and his money confiscated by the Thirty).

  • The court in which Socrates was tried
    • Religious matters were tried in courts under the jurisdiction of the King Archon. Athens had nine important magistracies (administrative offices) of which the King Archon was one. One of the duties of the King Archon was to supervise courts which heard charges of homicide and sacrilege. Before the democracy, archons actually heard and judged cases. Under the democracy, however, their role was purely administrative. Prosecutors brought their cases to the archons who decided in which court it was to be heard. The archons supervised pre-trial administrative matters and assigned the trial to a jury panel to be heard. They had no substantive role in the trial itself.

    • Socrates trial was held in the heliastic court, most likely before a jury of 501. The Heliaia were established by Solon and clearly important in the development of democracy at Athens. The word heliaia linguistically means assembly, but it may have meant in use, an assembly which hears judicial appeals (and thus limits the authority of the archons to decide lawsuits). It is very difficulty to distinguish between the functions of the heliaia and the dikasterion during the democratic period. Dikasterion is the ordinary Athenian word for "lawcourt." Each board of archons in the democracy had its own court, and the court of the archons called thesmothetai (who supervised trials of political cases) was called the heliaia. However, the word is occasionally used simply to mean, "the people's court," i.e. as a synomnym of dikasterion.

    • The archons managed a jury panel of 6,000 citizens which he divided up into smaller panels to hear cases. A typical jury was 501, but there is evidence of juries as small as 201 and as large as 1,001.

       


Trials Homepage

Course Requirements

Required Books

Syllabus

Course Description

Analysis Forms

Web Resources

Lecture Outlines

Discussion Questions

About the Prof

Imber's Homepage